1. New
  2. Home
    1. Get Started - Activities
    2. Posting Policies
    3. Community Standards
    4. Terms of Use
    5. Moderator Team
    6. Member Announcements
    7. Site Map
    8. Quizzes
    9. Articles
      1. Featured Articles
    10. All Blog Posts
      1. Elli's Blog / Articles
  3. Wiki
    1. Wiki Home
    2. FAQ
    3. Classical Epicureanism
    4. Physics
    5. Canonics
    6. Ethics
    7. Search Assistance
    8. Not NeoEpicurean
    9. Foundations
    10. Navigation Outlines
    11. Key Pages
  4. Forum
    1. New Activity
    2. New Threads
    3. Welcome
    4. General Discussion
    5. Featured
    6. Activism
    7. Shortcuts
    8. Dashboard
    9. Full Forum List
    10. Level 3+
    11. Most Discussed
  5. Podcast
    1. Lucretius Today Podcast
    2. Episode Guide
    3. Lucretius Today At Youtube
    4. EpicureanFriends Youtube Page
  6. Texts
    1. Overview
    2. Diogenes Laertius
    3. Principal Doctrines
    4. Vatican Sayings
    5. Lucretius
    6. Herodotus
    7. Pythocles
    8. Menoeceus
    9. Fragments - Usener Collection
    10. Torquatus On Ethics
    11. Velleius On Gods
    12. Greek/Latin Help
  7. Gallery
    1. Featured images
    2. Albums
    3. Latest Images
    4. Latest Comments
  8. Calendar
    1. Upcoming Events List
    2. Zoom Meetings
    3. This Month
    4. Sunday Zoom Meetings
    5. First Monday Zoom Meetings
    6. Wednesday Zoom Meeting
    7. Twentieth Zoom Meetings
    8. Zoom Meetings
  9. Other
    1. Featured Content
    2. Blog Posts
    3. Files
    4. Logbook
    5. EF ToDo List
    6. Link-Database
  • Login
  • Register
  • Search
This Thread
  • Everywhere
  • This Thread
  • This Forum
  • Forum
  • Articles
  • Blog Articles
  • Files
  • Gallery
  • Events
  • Pages
  • Wiki
  • Help
  • FAQ
  • More Options

Welcome To EpicureanFriends.com!

"Remember that you are mortal, and you have a limited time to live, and in devoting yourself to discussion of the nature of time and eternity you have seen things that have been, are now, and are to come."

Sign In Now
or
Register a new account
  1. New
  2. Home
    1. Get Started - Activities
    2. Posting Policies
    3. Community Standards
    4. Terms of Use
    5. Moderator Team
    6. Member Announcements
    7. Site Map
    8. Quizzes
    9. Articles
      1. Featured Articles
    10. All Blog Posts
      1. Elli's Blog / Articles
  3. Wiki
    1. Wiki Home
    2. FAQ
    3. Classical Epicureanism
    4. Physics
    5. Canonics
    6. Ethics
    7. Search Assistance
    8. Not NeoEpicurean
    9. Foundations
    10. Navigation Outlines
    11. Key Pages
  4. Forum
    1. New Activity
    2. New Threads
    3. Welcome
    4. General Discussion
    5. Featured
    6. Activism
    7. Shortcuts
    8. Dashboard
    9. Full Forum List
    10. Level 3+
    11. Most Discussed
  5. Podcast
    1. Lucretius Today Podcast
    2. Episode Guide
    3. Lucretius Today At Youtube
    4. EpicureanFriends Youtube Page
  6. Texts
    1. Overview
    2. Diogenes Laertius
    3. Principal Doctrines
    4. Vatican Sayings
    5. Lucretius
    6. Herodotus
    7. Pythocles
    8. Menoeceus
    9. Fragments - Usener Collection
    10. Torquatus On Ethics
    11. Velleius On Gods
    12. Greek/Latin Help
  7. Gallery
    1. Featured images
    2. Albums
    3. Latest Images
    4. Latest Comments
  8. Calendar
    1. Upcoming Events List
    2. Zoom Meetings
    3. This Month
    4. Sunday Zoom Meetings
    5. First Monday Zoom Meetings
    6. Wednesday Zoom Meeting
    7. Twentieth Zoom Meetings
    8. Zoom Meetings
  9. Other
    1. Featured Content
    2. Blog Posts
    3. Files
    4. Logbook
    5. EF ToDo List
    6. Link-Database
  1. New
  2. Home
    1. Get Started - Activities
    2. Posting Policies
    3. Community Standards
    4. Terms of Use
    5. Moderator Team
    6. Member Announcements
    7. Site Map
    8. Quizzes
    9. Articles
      1. Featured Articles
    10. All Blog Posts
      1. Elli's Blog / Articles
  3. Wiki
    1. Wiki Home
    2. FAQ
    3. Classical Epicureanism
    4. Physics
    5. Canonics
    6. Ethics
    7. Search Assistance
    8. Not NeoEpicurean
    9. Foundations
    10. Navigation Outlines
    11. Key Pages
  4. Forum
    1. New Activity
    2. New Threads
    3. Welcome
    4. General Discussion
    5. Featured
    6. Activism
    7. Shortcuts
    8. Dashboard
    9. Full Forum List
    10. Level 3+
    11. Most Discussed
  5. Podcast
    1. Lucretius Today Podcast
    2. Episode Guide
    3. Lucretius Today At Youtube
    4. EpicureanFriends Youtube Page
  6. Texts
    1. Overview
    2. Diogenes Laertius
    3. Principal Doctrines
    4. Vatican Sayings
    5. Lucretius
    6. Herodotus
    7. Pythocles
    8. Menoeceus
    9. Fragments - Usener Collection
    10. Torquatus On Ethics
    11. Velleius On Gods
    12. Greek/Latin Help
  7. Gallery
    1. Featured images
    2. Albums
    3. Latest Images
    4. Latest Comments
  8. Calendar
    1. Upcoming Events List
    2. Zoom Meetings
    3. This Month
    4. Sunday Zoom Meetings
    5. First Monday Zoom Meetings
    6. Wednesday Zoom Meeting
    7. Twentieth Zoom Meetings
    8. Zoom Meetings
  9. Other
    1. Featured Content
    2. Blog Posts
    3. Files
    4. Logbook
    5. EF ToDo List
    6. Link-Database
  1. EpicureanFriends - Home of Classical Epicurean Philosophy
  2. Forum
  3. Ethics - How To Live As An Epicurean
  4. Only Two Feelings - Pleasure and Pain - The Term Pleasure Includes Tranquility, Meaningfulness, Katastematic, Kinetic, Etc.
  • Sidebar
  • Sidebar

Do Pigs Value Katastematic Pleasure? ( Summer 2022 K / K Discussion)

  • Don
  • June 29, 2022 at 11:26 PM
  • Go to last post
Regularly Checking In On A Small Screen Device? Bookmark THIS page!
  • Don
    ΕΠΙΚΟΥΡΕΙΟΣ (Epicurist)
    Points
    39,870
    Posts
    5,551
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    92.8 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 12:19 AM
    • #121
    Quote from Cassius

    I know I seem like Negative Nellie here

    "Iron sharpens iron" as the saying goes. Keep the questions coming!

    Quote from Cassius

    wouldn't the pleasure you get from planning and carrying out some activity in expectation of the reward that the activity will bring be something that has to ring of "action"? I thought that katastematic was supposedly implying "rest" or "static."

    I'm coming to the understanding that it isn't necessarily an action like we think of "doing something". Look at that excerpt again,:

    Quote from Don

    Nor, (the Cyrenaics) say, is pleasure brought about through memory or expectation of goods, as Epicurus held: for the motion of the soul is obliterated by time’ (DL 2.89–90) (τὸ τῆς ψυχῆς κίνημα)

    The movement, the action, is the "motion of the soul (ψυχής psykhes)" that happens while one is *experiencing* a pleasure in the moment. It appears the Cyrenaics did not believe that their was any "motion of the soul" during "memory or expectation" of pleasure. The "motion" (κίνημα kinēma; related to kinesis, kinetic) only happened during the pleasure of the moment. Possibly "memory or expectation" was experienced in the "state", the soul/mind was "static." In fact, "the motion of the soul is obliterated by time." The motion of the soul stops - it is "obliterated." Stops= static. It is simply in a state of readiness to move again *with the next pleasure of the moment.* However, Epicurus taught that the pleasure of "memory or expectation" in that state *was* in fact just as much pleasure as that experienced in the moment.

    Granted, I need to read more Cyrenaic papers now (I didn't see that coming as necessary!), But the bit I've read from scanning the ones I've found, that's the direction I'm heading.

    FYI, here's another paper:

    Plutarch's Adversus Colotem and the Cyrenaics: 1120C-1121E
    Plutarch's Adversus Colotem and the Cyrenaics: 1120C-1121E
    www.academia.edu

    There are a number on Academia by Sedley, Warren, and others.

    And I'm deliberately staying away from Cicero until I can get some more sources, hopefully actual texts being quoted by other authors and not paraphrased into characters in Cicero's work.

    Fascinating stuff!

  • Don
    ΕΠΙΚΟΥΡΕΙΟΣ (Epicurist)
    Points
    39,870
    Posts
    5,551
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    92.8 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 12:47 AM
    • #122

    By the way, if this line of reasoning is correct, then the categories of katastematic and kinetic pleasures is irrelevant to a "modern" Epicurean because the Ancient Greek categories are built on a concept of the movement (or not) of "atoms" of the "soul/mind/psykhē" and that's *not" how our bodies and minds work.

    Don't misunderstand. It could be interesting in an historical sense in understanding the controversies and rivalries between schools. And it appears to have been vitally important to the ancients.

    But in applying the classical precepts to modern lives when we understand neurons and dopamine and so on, it's irrelevant. Epicurus would then have taught that ALL pleasure is pleasurable: in the moment, in anticipation, in remembrance. All of it. I do think he taught that freedom from pain and trouble in the body and mind was vitally important, but there's no injunction to ONLY experience that.

  • Don
    ΕΠΙΚΟΥΡΕΙΟΣ (Epicurist)
    Points
    39,870
    Posts
    5,551
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    92.8 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 1:00 AM
    • #123

    "He (sc. Aristippus the Younger) clearly defined pleasure as the end, inserting into his doctrine the concept of pleasure related to motion. For he said, there are three conditions (katastasesis) of our temperament: one, in which we are in pain, is like a storm at sea; another, in which we experience pleasure and which can be compared to a gentle wave, for pleasure is a gentle movement, similar to a fair wind; and the third is an intermediate condition, in which we experience neither pain nor pleasure, which is like a calm. He said we have perception of these affections alone (toutôn de kai ephasken tôn pathôn monôn hêmas tên aisthêsin echein). (F5 Chiesara=SSR IV A 173 and B5)."

    Source:

    Persons, Objects and Knowledge in the Cyrenaics.pdf
    The Cyrenaic views on persons, objects and knowledge.
    www.academia.edu

    Epicurus didn't accept this "third state". He included this "calm" under the category of pleasure. That's the katastematic pleasures.

    I realize I need to read more.

    Now I'm done for today... Oh, wait, it's already Saturday. I'm done for now then.

  • Online
    Cassius
    05 - Administrator
    Points
    102,623
    Posts
    14,049
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    100.0 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 5:10 AM
    • #124
    Quote from Don

    "Iron sharpens iron" as the saying goes. Keep the questions coming!

    Yes thank you Don - that is the key attitude and exactly the right frame of mind to bring to this discussion,

    The current "mainstream' discussion of K/K issues strikes me as the opposite of iron - it's like jelly or worse - and something that people assert to be as important as this - to take the place of pleasure itself in the discussion of Epicurus - very much needs to be sharpened down to a fine point so that it can be placed in proper perspective.

  • Don
    ΕΠΙΚΟΥΡΕΙΟΣ (Epicurist)
    Points
    39,870
    Posts
    5,551
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    92.8 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 7:48 AM
    • #125

    Compare my Arisocles/Eusebius quote in #123 (also available here at the end of chapter 18 for in situ context:

    Eusebius of Caesarea: Praeparatio Evangelica (Preparation for the Gospel). Tr. E.H. Gifford (1903) -- Book 14

    with Cicero in De Finibus:

    Quote

    For if he means the same as Hieronymus, who holds that the Chief Good is a life entirely devoid of trouble, why does he insist on using the term pleasure, and not rather 'freedom from pain,' as does Hieronymus, who understands his own meaning? Whereas if his view is that the End must include kinetic pleasure (for so he describes this vivid sort of pleasure, calling it 'kinetic' in contrary with the pleasure of freedom from pain, which is 'static' pleasure), what is he really aiming at? For he cannot possibly convince any person who knows himself5 — anyone who has studied his own nature and sensations — that freedom from pain is the same thing as pleasure. This, Torquatus, is to do violence to the senses — this uprooting from our minds our knowledge of the meaning of words ingrained. Who is not aware that the world of experience contains these three states of feeling: first, the enjoyment of pleasure; second, the sensation of pain; and third, which is my own condition and doubtless also yours at the present moment, the absence of both pleasure and pain? Pleasure is the feeling of a man eating a good dinner, pain that of one being broken on the rack; but do you really not see the intermediate between those two extremes lies a vast multitude of persons who are feeling neither gratification nor pain?" 17 "I certainly do not," said he; "I maintain that all who are without pain are enjoying pleasure, and what is more the highest form of pleasure." "Then you think that a man who, not being himself thirsty, mixes a drink for p99 another, feels the same pleasure as the thirsty man who drinks it?"

    So, they're all feeding off each other, pointing back to earlier sources:

    Cicero 106–43 BC

    Aristocles of Messene 1st-century CE

    Eusebius 260 – 339 CE

    To reply to your post, Cassius :

    Quote from Cassius

    something that people assert to be as important as this - to take the place of pleasure itself in the discussion of Epicurus - very much needs to be sharpened down to a fine point so that it can be placed in proper perspective

    Katastematic pleasure isn't taking the place of pleasure per se. They're redefining pleasure in an almost Ciceronian way and substitute their definition for pleasure writ large. Many of the "mainstream" commentators are ONLY focusing on that third state - the calm, the absence - that Epicurus included within his definition of pleasure when he rejected there was a neutral state with no motion of the soul atoms. He said, in strong opposition to the Cyrenaic position (and others), that there is no neutral state. That state - the freedom from pain and trouble in the body and mind - is included in Epicurus's definition of pleasure. There is only pleasure OR pain, full stop. That *feeling* of calm, of the stable well-functioning state of body and mind, IS pleasurable. But Epicurus included ALL pleasures within the definition of Pleasure, whether "kinetic" when the soul-atoms were in motion in the moment, whether one was remembering or anticipating a past or future pleasure, or whether one was experiencing the absence of pain and trouble in body and mind. I'm going to posit (for now) that those last two categories of pleasure fall under "katastematic" pleasure. Furthermore, wherever Epicurus is writing about calm, freedom from pain or trouble in body or mind, remembering or anticipating pleasure, etc. that he's writing about katastematic pleasure whether the word gets used or not. For him, I believe, there was a distinction without a difference. It was all pleasure and so all of it fell under the descriptor of "good." The problems arise with some desires for specific pleasures that led to pain, or pleasures at certain times that were unwise or not prudent. We make better decisions when we're calm and working well in body and mind and that, I think, is why Epicurus laid an importance of emphasis on that aspect, but ALL pleasures were within the realm of consideration in context and choices.

  • Online
    Cassius
    05 - Administrator
    Points
    102,623
    Posts
    14,049
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    100.0 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 10:59 AM
    • #126

    I think we're generally in agreement except for this part....

    Quote from Don

    Furthermore, wherever Epicurus is writing about calm, freedom from pain or trouble in body or mind, remembering or anticipating pleasure, etc. that he's writing about katastematic pleasure whether the word gets used or not.

    ...because I see no evidence in the core Epicurean texts that the Epicureans got around to mentioning the word "katastematic" except at best in rare instances. The idea that "absence of pain" equals katastematic pleasure seems to be an unwanted assumption. When the focus on life is pleasure, and you crowd out pains by replacing them with pleasures of all types, then there is no need to be concerned about what would happen if you attempted to bury yourself in a sensory deprivation chamber and somehow drained yourself if pains without replacing those pains with some form of mental or physical activity.

    Cicero is attempting to go back to Plato's argument that pleasure cannot be continuous by insisting that if you aren't being stimulated in some way then you aren't experiencing pleasure. The very example he gives - of engaging in philosophic debate - has no need to be considered a hard case or a neutral state, because the mind is engaged in intense activity on an important subject - just like we are now - and we are experiencing a definite type of pleasure in hunting down the answers, even if there is much effort involved.

    To me this argument from Cicero makes clear the problem in the whole "absence of pain" and "katastematic pleasure issue.". It is much more direct to consider all mental and physical consciousness of life to be pleasurable unless it involves significant pain, and thereby you never have to quibble about some "fancy pleasure" state that seems exotic and esoteric.

    The discussion continues to convince me that the whole issue arises due to the desire of the anti-Epicureans to find a way to hijack Epicurus' focus on pleasure because they will not accept that pleasure as commonly understood is in fact desirable. They want to substitute their own "virtue-approved" definition for pleasure.

    Epicurus had a clear and important reason for his sweeping definition of pleasure - to show how pleasure of some kind (including situations that seem to involve only calm reflection) is always available to be referenced as the guide of life. His enemies took this sweeping definition and decided to elevate the calm reflection part (which they consider themselves to be kings of) as the ultimate goal. They did this by taking Epicurus' accurate observation - that when you have filled your life full of pleasure you cannot add any more because you are full - and took it out of context to adopt the "absence of pain" part as if it were something in itself, which it is not.

    It is essential and important to explain to people that Pleasure in life comes through any kind of positive mental or physical activity that you don't find painful, including calm reflection. The contrast is made vivid by comparing it with the nothingness of availability of feeling after death. That part I think we are all agreed on.

    But is it necessary to explain as a part of core Epicurean teaching the difference between kinetic and katastematic? The core texts don't, and even Torquatus himself, in his main narrative explaining Epicurean ethics, does not so much as mention the issue. It is only when it is used as an attack point by Cicero that Torquatus may address it at all. Lucretius and Philodemus, devoted advocates of the core, are also silent on it.

    The value I am seeing in this conversation is that it is reinforcing to me that the entire katastematic/ kinetic discussion needs to be ejected from presentations of core Epicurean philosophy. Its main use going forward into the future in the presentation of an Epicurean curriculum should be to teach advanced students how the argument was used over the last two thousand years to relegate Epicurus into the corner of being a philosopher for nursing homes, and which thereby ejected from the largest part of normal healthy life. In that context the discussion is absolutely essential.

    If one forces Hercules to spend every moment of his life clipping his toenails then even the physical strength and mental a acuity of a Hercules becomes absolutely neutered. There is no better way to sap the vitality from Epicurus as a savior of mankind than to force him to spin around endlessly in a word game like a dog chasing its own tale. I fully believe that Cicero saw just that opportunity, and his example has been followed ever since. No Epicurus in the camp, no Epicurus in the Senate, and no Epicurus anywhere in real human life.

  • Don
    ΕΠΙΚΟΥΡΕΙΟΣ (Epicurist)
    Points
    39,870
    Posts
    5,551
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    92.8 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 11:31 AM
    • #127

    Sorry, don't have time to read your full post right now. I will!

    But Epicurus literally defined katastematic pleasure as ataraxia (freedom from trouble in the mind) and aponia (freedom of pain in the body).

    My contention is that anytime those concepts come up in his and other Epicurean writings, they're talking about katastematic pleasure. They don't use the word because it's not necessary. By definition: freedom from trouble in the mind and freedom of pain in the body = katastematic pleasure.

    They don't mention the term every time because it really didn't matter to them. It was a tautology: pleasure = pleasure.

  • Don
    ΕΠΙΚΟΥΡΕΙΟΣ (Epicurist)
    Points
    39,870
    Posts
    5,551
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    92.8 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 12:24 PM
    • #128
    Quote from Cassius

    I see no evidence in the core Epicurean texts that the Epicureans got around to mentioning the word "katastematic" except at best in rare instances.

    Sure, rare, but:

    Quote

    The words of Epicurus in his work On Choice are : "Peace of mind and freedom from pain are pleasures which imply a state of rest ; joy and delight are seen to consist in motion and activity."

    ὁ δ᾽ Ἐπίκουρος ἐν τῷ Περὶ αἱρέσεων οὕτω λέγει: "ἡ μὲν γὰρ ἀταραξία καὶ ἀπονία καταστηματικαί εἰσιν ἡδοναί: ἡ δὲ χαρὰ καὶ ἡ εὐφροσύνη κατὰ κίνησιν ἐνεργείᾳ βλέπονται."

  • Eikadistes
    Garden Bard
    Points
    14,574
    Posts
    848
    Quizzes
    3
    Quiz rate
    94.7 %
    Bookmarks
    10
    • July 16, 2022 at 12:38 PM
    • #129

    An excerpt from “Epicureans, Earlier Atomists, and Cyrenaics” by Stefano Maso:

    “According to Epicurus this is happiness, technically the katastematic pleasure:

    the well-established condition or state of the body in which pleasure does not change (On

    the Goal, fr. 22.3 Arrighetti).

    [...]

    It is crucial to note that natural but non-necessary desires are based on the varying of the

    perceptual experience.

    These various forms of desire are precisely what enable Epicurus to develop a conception

    of pleasure that distinguishes between kinetic pleasure [kata kinêsin hêdonê] and static or

    katastematic pleasure [katastêmatikê hêdonê]. The kind of pleasure that varies constitutes

    the explicit foundation of Cyrenaic thought: Cyrenaics do not admit katastematic pleasure.

    By contrast, Epicurus accepts both kinds of pleasure and assures his readers that freedom

    from disturbance [ataraxia] and absence of pain [aponia] are static pleasure; but joy

    [chara] and delight [euphrosunê] are regarded as kinetic activities (DL 10.137).

    It seems as though the unbridled physical enjoyment of pleasure constitutes the heart of

    the Cyrenaics’ hedonistic ethics. The pursuit of pleasure thus translates, in their view, into

    the experiencing of a pleasure that varies in terms of both quality and intensity. The corollary

    to this is that, precisely because there is no limit to the quality and intensity of

    pleasure, the pleasure of the Cyrenaics proves disappointing, since it endlessly defers the

    possibility of satisfaction.

    According to the Cyrenaics, we can distinguish three states: one in which we are in pain,

    and which is like a storm at sea; a second one in which we experience pleasure, and which

    is like a gentle swell—for pleasure is a smooth movement; and a third, intermediate state in

    which we feel neither pain nor pleasure, and which is like a flat calm (PE 14.18.32 = IVB5

    Giannantoni). Man seems to perceive these three states alone; moreover, from the Cyrenaics’

    perspective, it is pointless to carry the enquiry any further, for example by searching

    for the cause of these different states.

    By contrast—and evidently in polemical opposition to the Cyrenaics—the Epicureans

    believe that pleasure is pleasure, and pain is pain and that there can be no intermediate state

    between them. Pleasure is found where there is and for as long as there is no pain, just as

    pain is found where there is no pleasure and as long as there is no pleasure: the removal of

    all pain is the limit of the magnitude of pleasures (KD 3–4; LS 21C). Moreover, every

    pleasure qua pleasure is good, and every pain qua pain is bad (Ep. Men. 129; LS 21B3).

    But how is it possible to deny the existence of an intermediate state, a state that everyday

    human experience seems to entail? Why does Epicurus choose to go down this route?

    We can try to answer by relying on the interpretation Cicero gives us of the controversy

    between Democritus, Cyrenaics and Epicureans. While this interpretation clearly derives

    from doxographical contributions, there is no doubt it reflects a historical and persistent

    rivalry between the different schools.

    Cicero—a critical yet attentive reader of Epicurean texts—tackles the issue we have

    posed directly, especially in Book 2 of De finibus and Book 3 of the Tusculanae disputationes.

    18 First of all, Cicero believes that Epicurus contradicts himself, because in his

    view the philosopher believes not so much that the absence of pain can accompany the

    absence of pleasure, but rather that pleasure and the absence of pain de facto coincide,

    constituting a sort of analgesic hedonism (cf. Tusc. 3.47 = KD 18). Therefore, the ultimate

    good would simultaneously coincide with the absence of pain and the highest degree of

    pleasure. Furthermore, Cicero emphasizes that, in his approach to ethics, Epicurus has

    separated the highest good (which coincides with pleasure) from virtue. In doing so, he has

    created an unbridgeable gulf between the physical and the spiritual dimension. Cicero’s

    ultimate thesis is the diametric opposite: “Pleasure is one thing, absence from suffering

    quite another [aliud est voluptas, aliud non dolere].”19 In other words, suffering is the

    opposite of its own absence, and not the opposite of pleasure (De Fin. 2.28). Cicero here is

    adopting the thesis of Hieronymus of Rhodes, the Peripatetic philosopher (third century

    BCE), according to whom the experience of pleasure and the absence of pain are two different things (De Fin. 2.9).

    To avoid possible misunderstandings, Cicero introduces an

    example: he asks whether the pleasure we feel when drinking is the same as that which we

    experience after having quenched our thirst. The answer is very important: according to

    Torquatus (the champion of the Epicurean thesis in Cicero’s dialogue), once our thirst has

    been quenched, we enjoy a stable pleasure; whereas during the actual act of quenching our

    thirst we experience an unstable pleasure, i.e. a pleasure in movement (De Fin. 2.9–10).

    However, this means assigning the same name, pleasure, to two different kinds of pleasure;

    and, according to Cicero, this is incorrect, as is the notion of “variation” [varietas] when it

    is introduced to deny the radical difference between stable pleasure and kinetic pleasure. It

    is untenable to argue that kinetic pleasure (i.e. pleasure that “varies”) must be added to and

    coincide with stable pleasure, which “does not vary” (i.e. “absence from suffering”).

    According to Cicero, Epicurus’ theory resembles an attempt to combine Hieronymus’

    theory with that of the Cyrenaic Aristippus (De Fin. 2.19)—an absurdity.

    By contrast, precisely the connection between “stability” and “perception” is key to

    explaining the reason the Epicureans theorized the absoluteness of “katastematic pleasure,”

    namely the kind of pleasure that does not vary. Epicurus himself would appear to

    have been the first to draw a distinction between the two kinds of pleasure (DL 10.136 =

    LS 21R), by emphasizing that only the former is perfect and lasting, whereas the latter is

    temporary. The instability of kinetic pleasure, and its reduction to a mere physical condition

    to be brought back to stability (which is to say, to katastematic pleasure), is the key

    to understanding the Epicurean position. Reason is what brings this “reduction” about: it

    rests on the realization that variation—which constitutes kinetic pleasure—is actually

    entirely superfluous, given that any experience of freedom from pain coincides with the

    highest good: “pleasure exists everywhere, and for the entire time it lasts, there is no

    suffering either of body or of mind or both” (KD 3). This implies that the intermediate

    state—the one which, according to Hieronymus and Cicero, makes the absence of pain

    different from the presence of pleasure, even though the two may go hand in hand—is

    meaningless, which is why Epicurus rejects it.

    It may be noted that the ancient atomists did not distinguish between the two kinds of

    pleasure. Rather, Democritus observed that the ultimate goal which man must set himself is

    contentment [euthymia]: only by finding satisfaction in what we have and what is proper to

    our nature, and by appreciating what befalls us, can we attain safety and absence of

    apprehension [athambia], and well-being (Stobaeus, Anthology 3.1.210, LM 27D226–231 =

    DK 68B3, 189, 191; A1, 167, 169. See 133.1–4, 152.1–4, 139.1, 137.1 Leszl). “Contentment”

    seems to foreshadow katastematic pleasure, insofar as it consists in the capacity to

    limit desire and pleasure. We can ask if a specific connotation distinguishes the denominations

    with which Clement of Alexandria20 labels the ultimate end [telos] that Democritus’

    successors identified. And whereas Democritus identifies telos with euthymia or euestô

    (contentment and feeling good), Nausyphanes (Epicurus’ teacher) uses the word akataplêxia

    (absence of fright). But according to Clement, the akataplêxia of Nausyphanes corresponds

    to the athambia (absence of apprehension) attributed to Democritus. Furthermore,

    Anaxarchus of Abdera, one of the first followers of Democritus, proposed the apatheia (the

    absence of passions) and the adiaphoria (the indifference to external things) as means to

    reach the eudaimonia (happiness). However, it is evident that only Democritus defines telos

    (the ultimate end/the purpose) positively: all the other words are qualified by the presence

    of the “privative alpha”—a prefix meant to indicate the negation of a word—and seem to

    allude to happiness as the result of a process of “reduction” in the human psycho-physical

    experience, the exact process that can also be recognized in the way Epicurus conceives of

    katastematic pleasure.

    The Cyrenaics’ interpretation of pleasure leads them instead to acknowledge the distinction

    between the two kinds of pleasure. However, this theory denies that it is de facto

    possible to grant katastematic pleasure. Given the varied and successive way in which we

    experience pleasures, we can grasp only kinetic pleasure or katastematic pleasure, either

    successively or not at all, and any increase in pleasure is kinetic.

    Unlike that of the Cyrenaics, Epicurus and Lucretius’s interpretation is intended as a

    renewed version of Democritus’ position. By introducing a distinction between two different

    kinds of pleasure, the Epicureans also reach another remarkable conclusion: the idea

    that contentment is already a katastematic pleasure in itself. Clearly, it is possible to grasp

    different facets of such pleasure, which present themselves as varietas and hence as kinetic

    pleasure. Epicurus and Lucretius are aware that it is the task of reason to process this varied

    sensory experience, in such a way that each specific detail may be positively appreciated

    and grasped in the most pregnant possible way [katapuknôsis]. Epicurus gives great weight

    to cogitation [logismos and phronesis] and, ultimately, reason (which is to say the mind,

    psuchê), demanding that they be capable of grasping and focusing on the pleasurable

    aspects of life, so that negative ones may be considered absent (and be de facto eliminated).

    But if the physical side of the experience of pleasure constitutes the point of departure, the

    point of arrival is the rational processing of this experience. In The Letter to Menoeceus

    (129–130 = LS 21B3) Epicurus writes:

    Every pleasure, because of its natural affinity, is something good, yet not every

    pleasure is choice worthy. Correspondingly, every pain is something bad, but not

    every pain is by nature to be avoided. However, we have to make our judgment on

    all these points by a calculation and survey of advantages and disadvantages. For

    at certain times we treat the good as bad and conversely the bad as good.

    Consequently, Epicurus—opposing the Cyrenaics—can argue that, even in the apparently

    most painful moments, the wise man is capable of being happy: for, if needs be, he knows

    how to concentrate on the sheer fact of being alive. At this point, “being alive” may be

    seen to coincide with katastematic pleasure. Epicurus states as much in a letter to his

    mother: “When we are alive, we experience a joy akin to that of the gods” (PHerc. 176 5

    X Vogliano = fr. 72.38–40 Arrighetti). Even his spiritual testament, which is to say the

    letter addressed to his friend Idomeneus and transmitted by Diogenes Laertius, bears

    witness to this. The philosopher maintains that the day in which he is dying is a blessed

    one, even though his bladder and bowl pains could hardly be more intense (Letter to

    Idomeneus = DL 10.22).

    Aristippus’ Hedonic Presentism and Epicurus’ Doctrine of Limits

    According to the Cyrenaic Aristippus, pleasure persists and has value only as long as we

    are experiencing it. His grandson, Aristippus the Younger, thinks that a “unitemporal”

    present pleasure constitutes de facto the happiness that every man must propose to himself

    as an end. No doubt that this experience of pleasure is, moreover, an essentially physical

    experience. We observe that there is a strong emphasis on the physical dimension and the

    instantaneousness of the perception of pleasure; it is a real limitation that aims to capture

    only the most obvious character of pleasure: intensity. The Cyrenaics renounce the lasting

    experience of pleasure because their focus is the intensity of the instant in which man

    experiences pleasure. The Cyrenaics focus on the search for an ever more intense and

    varied experience of pleasure in order to guarantee the intensity of the present perception

    and avoid the distraction involved in waiting for an uncertain future. Kinetic pleasure is the

    actual limit of the Cyrenaic ethics.

    By contrast, it is important to understand the ethical basis of Epicurus’ doctrine, and, in

    particular, its therapeutic proposal. Every Epicurean master and every reader of Epicurean

    texts considers the “fourfold cure” [tetrapharmakos] a crucial element in Epicurean doctrine.

    Lucretius himself, while not directly referring to this doctrine, no doubt bore it in

    mind when composing his poem. Cicero explicitly mentions the Key Doctrines in which

    Epicurus summed it up. Even Philodemus of Gadara explicitly mentions the theory.25 Epicurus

    pithily expressed it as follows: “Were we not upset by the worries that celestial

    phenomena and death might matter to us, and also by failure to appreciate the limits of

    pains and desires, we would have no need for natural philosophy” (KD 11 = LS 25.B.11;

    cfr. KD 1–4, 10, 20, and Ep. Men. 133).

    It is interesting to note that the tetrapharmakos also rests on a doctrine of the “limit”; this

    time, however, in an Epicurean version. This doctrine applies to everything that exists and

    is perceived within the cosmos. Take atoms: we have isolated atoms that eternally fall and

    never combine with others; but we also have atoms that combine into endless, more or less

    changeable structures. The gods constitute the ultimate “limit” of this changeability, for

    they are eternally stable atomic compounds. They never change because, by definition, they

    are intangible: they never collide with other atoms or other compounds. Take death: by

    definition, it never has anything to do with life. It constitutes the “limit” of life. Take pain

    and, in parallel, pleasure: each constitutes the other’s “limit.”

    Based on this doctrine of the “limit,” Epicurus infers that we must not fear the gods,

    because they are imperturbable and, hence, take no interest in us or interfere with other

    atomic compounds (Ep. Men. 123–124). We must not fear death, because when it exists, we

    do not; and as long as we are alive, we cannot perceive it (Ep. Men. 124–127). We must

    not fear pain, because it may be more or less intense: if it is light, it is so easily endurable

    that at its limit it can be perceived as pleasure; if it is extreme, a loss of sensibility occurs

    and we no longer feel it (KD 4). Finally, we must not fear pleasure, in the sense that we

    must not fear the dissatisfaction that affects those who give themselves over to the pursuit

    of the most intense and prolonged sort of kinetic pleasure, as did the Cyrenaics, for kinetic

    pleasure finds its limit in katastematic pleasure (Ep. Men. 131–132).

    This is exactly the opposite of what the Cyrenaics claim. Although both consider the

    “limit” as an inevitable psychophysical border, the experience of the limit leads the Cyrenaics

    to renounce katastematic pleasure, denying its reason; on the contrary, it leads Epicurus

    and the Epicureans to re-evaluate katastematic pleasure by reconsidering kinetic

    pleasure as an irrelevant variable.”

    (Maso, Stefano. “Epicureans, Earlier Atomists, and Cyrenaics”. The Routledge Handbook of Hellenistic Philosophy, edited by Kelly Arenson. Routledge, 2020, 60-65)

  • Eikadistes
    Garden Bard
    Points
    14,574
    Posts
    848
    Quizzes
    3
    Quiz rate
    94.7 %
    Bookmarks
    10
    • July 16, 2022 at 12:39 PM
    • #130

    An excerpt from “Epicureans on Pleasure, Desire, and Happiness” by B. A. Rider:

    “Epicurus’ second important distinction between types of pleasure was more original and

    challenging, and its interpretation remains controversial. Epicurus evidently distinguished

    between kinetic pleasures—those involving some kind of “movement [kinesis]”—and

    katastematic (or static) pleasures (from “katastema” referring to a condition of equilibrium)—

    those arising from the healthy state of the body and mind, free from pain and

    disturbance. This distinction cuts across the previous one. Epicurean texts mention both

    mental and bodily kinetic pleasures, and mental and bodily katastematic pleasures (see, e.g.,

    DL 10.136).

    This distinction was important because, Epicurus argues, the pleasures that matter for

    eudaimonia are katastematic ones: the health and painless state of the body [aponia] and

    the tranquility of the mind (ataraxia—literally “freedom from disturbance [tarache]”) (Ep.

    Men. 128; KD 3, 18). Epicurus uses this idea to argue that pleasure has a limit. Once your

    body and mind are in a good state, the quality of your experience of life cannot be

    improved—it is as good as it can get. At this point, there is no need for more food, luxury,

    or indulgence, because adding more cannot make your life any better, and it may even

    damage your ability to experience health and tranquility in the long term.

    […]

    Later, Cicero contends that the arguments supporting Epicureanism depend on a fallacy of

    equivocation, using “pleasure” ambiguously to make their position appear more attractive

    than it is. He criticizes Epicurus’ appeal to the behavior of infants:

    What sort of pleasure, static [katastematic] or kinetic […] will the bawling infant

    use to determine the supreme good and evil? If static, then clearly its natural

    instinct is for self-preservation, which I accept. If kinetic, as you in fact claim, then

    there will be no pleasure too foul to be experienced. Moreover, our new-born

    creature will not be starting from the highest pleasure, which you regard as the

    absence of pain.

    Admittedly, infants and uncorrupted animals want to feel good; they desire sensory stimulation,

    kinetic pleasure. But if so, how can the baby’s behavior be evidence that katastematic

    pleasure is the highest good? By conflating two very different kinds of experience

    and calling both “pleasure,” Cicero believes, Epicurus seeks illicitly to combine the crude

    enticements of indulgent hedonism with the moderation and order of a theory that aims for

    satisfied painlessness. Cicero suggests that while such a bait-and-switch sales pitch appeals

    to the shallow minded, it fails as a coherent and livable ethical theory.

    Is Cicero’s criticism fair? In part, the issue turns on how exactly we are meant to

    understand the distinction between kinetic and katastematic pleasures, and what precisely

    Epicureans had in mind in identifying aponia and ataraxia as the highest good. Unfortunately,

    on this point the surviving texts are especially fragmentary and contradictory, leaving

    open a variety of interpretations.

    Since Cicero’s On Moral Ends has the most detailed description of the doctrine, many

    interpreters use it as a starting point (including Long and Sedley 1987; Mitsis 1988; Woolf

    2009). According to Cicero, Epicureans classify any pleasure that actively stimulates the

    senses as kinetic, involving a “movement” in sensation (De Fin. 2.10, 2.16). These sensory,

    kinetic pleasures include both appetite satisfactions that fill deficiencies like hunger (what

    we might call “restorative” pleasures) and pleasant sensations that do not fill a deficiency,

    such as the pleasures of hearing beautiful music or seeing a beautiful statue (“non-restorative”).

    This breakdown leaves katastematic pleasure as simply the state of being free from

    pain or mental disturbance. This state does not in itself “stimulate the senses” (which would

    make it kinetic); but we recognize that it is good because of the relief we receive when pain

    or distress abates (1.37).

    Notice that Cicero’s way of drawing the distinction plays directly into his criticisms—if

    only kinetic pleasures involve sensory stimulation, it becomes puzzling why katastematic

    pleasure is pleasure and why we should think of it as being the goal. Moreover, Epicurus

    clearly places great importance on sensory pleasure. As quoted above, he claims that he

    “cannot conceive of anything as good” without the pleasures of taste, sight, sound, and

    sex (Cicero, Tusc. III.18.41 = LS 21L1). But if Cicero’s interpretation of the distinction

    between kinetic and katastematic pleasures is right, these are kinetic pleasures, and why

    would he care so much about inferior, kinetic pleasures? If the mere state of being free

    from pain itself represents the highest limit of quality experience, why would an Epicurean

    need them?

    For this reason, many scholars look for other ways to interpret the distinction. The debate

    about this topic has produced a dizzying array of interpretations. For the purposes of this

    chapter, I will describe just a few of the most prominent proposals.

    An early attempt to reconsider the distinction between kinetic and katastematic pleasures

    was made first by Diano 1935 and later by Rist 1972; Wolfsdorf 2009 defended this

    interpretation more recently. This interpretation accepts that all sensory pleasures are

    kinetic—they are “events in which the perceptual or rational faculties are smoothly or

    gently stimulated or activated” (252). But, on this interpretation, katastematic pleasure—

    the well-balanced state of body and mind—is the necessary precondition for any kinetic

    pleasure. A person cannot experience kinetic pleasures in a part of himself unless that part

    is in a pain- and disturbance-free state. Wolfsdorf explains, “perceptual pleasures [which

    are kinetic] reveal katastematic pleasures […] because perceptual pleasures depend on

    katastematic pleasures. The smooth functioning of the perceptual faculties indicates the

    correlative katastematic conditions” (245). Proponents of this interpretation focus on

    passages like Principal Doctrine 3, where Epicurus states, “As long as pleasure is present,

    so long as it is present, there is no pain, either of body or soul or both at once”

    (Wolfsdorf’s translation, 246). This interpretation allows for aponia and ataraxia to be

    fundamental (you can’t have any pleasure without them), while still taking into account

    Epicurus’ statements about the importance of sensory pleasures (since we need sensory

    pleasures to “reveal” the healthy state).

    As an illustration, consider someone who is hungry. He is hungry, Lucretius explains

    (DRN 2.963–72), because certain parts of his body are disturbed and out of place and

    require replenishment to restore their integrity and functioning. So he eats. As he eats, he

    feels pleasure on his palate and throat (from tasting and swallowing the food) but that is

    only because these parts aren’t disrupted. As the atoms from the food are absorbed into the

    body and the deficiency is remedied, the pain of hunger recedes. Wolfsdorf argues that the

    recession of hunger is not itself pleasurable, but it leaves us in a state that is free from pain

    and therefore capable of (kinetic) pleasure (252).

    On this picture, then, katastematic pleasure is a state of healthy functioning, and it is a

    precondition for any pleasurable stimulation. Kinetic pleasure occurs when healthy, painfree

    parts are “moved” and stimulated. What I’ve called “restorative pleasures,” however,

    don’t exist, because there can be no pleasure while parts being restored are still in pain.

    This interpretation has a possible problem—since it assumes, with Cicero, that all sensory

    pleasures are kinetic, it suffers some of the same objections: If only kinetic pleasures

    have a sensory quality, what is attractive about the katastematic pleasure in itself? On the

    Diano-Rist-Wolfsdorf picture, it starts to look like we seek a well-balanced state merely as

    means to experience kinetic pleasures. Moreover, why call the katastematic state “pleasure”?

    Finally, Epicurus insists that all good and bad occur in sensation (Ep. Men. 124), so

    how do we perceive the goodness of aponia and ataraxia, if they have no sensory quality

    of their own? For these reasons, Gosling and Taylor 1982 argue for a different interpretation.

    They contend that, actually, aponia and ataraxia are states of sensory pleasure:

    Aponia is a condition of having sensory pleasures but with no accompanying pain,

    and ataraxia is the state of confidence that one may acquire such sensory pleasures

    with complete absence of pain. This confidence is itself a positive state.…What is

    important is to get a life of sensory pleasure untainted by pain.

    When a person is conscious in a healthy, well-balanced state, Gosling and Taylor explain,

    she naturally experiences a wide variety of positive sensations: she feels warm and comfortable;

    tastes foods; hears sounds; enjoys the sights of things around herself. These

    experiences are not kinetic, as Cicero or Wolfsdorf assume, but are themselves manifestations

    of katastematic pleasure. Distinctively kinetic pleasures, on their view, are merely the

    subset of sensory pleasures involved in restoration or replenishment (373). In fact, Gosling

    and Taylor believe that, for Epicureans themselves, the distinction between kinetic and

    katastematic pleasures wasn’t really that important. It does not mark two vastly different

    kinds of pleasures, since both are sensory. The categorization has more to do with a pleasure’s

    functional role than its inherent qualities (374).

    Arenson’s recent book on Epicurean pleasure (Arenson 2019) updates and adds additional

    nuance to Gosling and Taylor’s approach. She agrees that the Epicureans’ main

    concern was with healthy functioning, and she traces Epicurus’ ideas to debates in Plato’s

    Academy, including Eudoxus and Aristotle, about the role of pleasure and healthy functioning

    in a good human life. Plato takes a strong anti-hedonist position: In the Philebus,

    Plato’s Socrates argues that pleasure cannot be the good, because pleasure occurs only in

    the process of filling a deficiency (53c-55c). Therefore, pleasure itself isn’t the good, but

    instead a means to a good end: healthy functioning.

    According to Arenson, Epicurus introduces the distinction between kinetic and katastematic

    pleasures in part to address these kinds of anti-hedonistic argument. Plato was right

    that some pleasures—kinetic pleasures—occur in the process of restoration, and these

    pleasures are indeed merely a means to a greater end. But, against the anti-hedonists, Epicurus

    argues that other pleasures—katastematic pleasures—arise from the healthy functioning

    itself. Arenson goes on to argue that katastematic pleasure itself has two

    manifestations: First, a general pleasurable quality of experience from having body and

    mind in a good state—a sort of non-specific pleasure of being alive, conscious, and healthy

    (Chapter 6). Second, there are pleasures that arise from specific activities of healthy faculties,

    including pleasures of seeing, hearing, and tasting. Arenson calls these “non-restorative

    pleasures,” because while they involve active stimulation, they do not restore deficiencies,

    as happens when we eat while hungry or drink while thirsty (Chapter 8). Now, these two

    manifestations of katastematic pleasure are not really distinct; rather, in line with Epicurus’

    doctrine that the highest pleasure has a limit, the non-restorative pleasures merely “vary”

    but do not add to the general quality of life (KD 18).

    […]

    I would suggest that the Epicureans understood this lesson, and that by defining the best

    experience of life as aponia and ataraxia, they aimed to capture something like this idea.

    Haybron’s attunement dimension corresponds most closely to Epicurean katastematic pleasure:

    both refer to a fundamental state of healthy functioning, security, and freedom from

    disturbance that makes other kinds of enjoyment possible. Epicurus realized that when a

    person’s mind and body are in a healthy, well-balanced state, it becomes possible for them

    to become engrossed in and enjoy a variety of different kinds of activities and experiences

    as expressions of that healthy state. Far from being ad hoc, then, Epicurus’ idiosyncratic

    form of hedonism may simply have been the right way to think about what makes for a

    good experience of life.”

    (Rider, B. A.. “Epicureans on Pleasure, Desire, and Happiness”. The Routledge Handbook of Hellenistic Philosophy, edited by Kelly Arenson. Routledge, 2020, 286-91)

  • Online
    Cassius
    05 - Administrator
    Points
    102,623
    Posts
    14,049
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    100.0 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 1:00 PM
    • #131

    Wow that is quite a collection thank you Nate!

    Quote from Nate

    For this reason, many scholars look for other ways to interpret the distinction. The debate

    about this topic has produced a dizzying array of interpretations. For the purposes of this

    chapter, I will describe just a few of the most prominent proposals.

    THAT (underlined sentence) is for sure!!!

    After reading all that I am still at the point ---

    "Categorize the pleasures and experience them however you see fit, the guide of life is the feeling of pleasure, not virtue, not religion, not abstract logic."

  • Online
    Cassius
    05 - Administrator
    Points
    102,623
    Posts
    14,049
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    100.0 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 2:06 PM
    • #132


    Please correct me if I am wrong, but in addition to being "rare" this is a statement by Diogenes Laertius, which we may presume to be a quote, but of which we don't for sure have an original sentence by Epicurus, or surrounding context.

    That observation (absence of a clear original where we see Epicurus making the point in full context) is a key aspect of the criticism of Nikolsky/Gosling/Taylor) in pointing out that it is Diogenese Laertius and Cicero who bring this issue to our attention, not its prominence in original works of Epicurus or core Epicureans.

    So we if are categorizing the main objections, they include, not necessarily in this order:

    - Rare at best.

    - Not featured as important in clear writings by core Epicureans

    ....and then combined with....

    - All of the textual consistency issues that arise from any implication that Epicurus valued "katastematic" more (or even equal to) than "kinetic" pleasure.

  • Don
    ΕΠΙΚΟΥΡΕΙΟΣ (Epicurist)
    Points
    39,870
    Posts
    5,551
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    92.8 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 2:30 PM
    • #133
    Quote from Cassius

    Please correct me if I am wrong, but in addition to being "rare" this is a statement by Diogenes Laertius

    Not from my reading. The original specifically says "And Epicurus in On Choices says as follows..." Then gives the quote.

  • Eikadistes
    Garden Bard
    Points
    14,574
    Posts
    848
    Quizzes
    3
    Quiz rate
    94.7 %
    Bookmarks
    10
    • July 16, 2022 at 2:40 PM
    • #134

    I am gravitating toward privileging the idea that "Epicurean texts mention both mental and bodily kinetic pleasures, and mental and bodily katastematic pleasures", which creates more of a spectrum than a strict duality:

    Kata Kinêsin HêdonêKatastêmatikê Hêdonê
    BodilyAponia
    MentalAtaraxia

    Others seem to argue for a horizontal division:

    Kata KinêsinKatastêmatikê
    Hêdonê

    Others advance this into a vertical hierarchy:

    1.Katastêmatikê Hêdonê
    2.Kata Kinêsin Hêdonê

    Others seem to propose an equivalency between desires and types of pleasure:

    HêdonêÈpithymiōn
    1.KatastêmatikêPhysikaì kai ànagkaîai (natural and necessary)
    2. Kata KinêsinPhysikaì kai oyk ànagkaîai (natural and not necessary)

    There seems to be a further suggestion that the division between katastematic and kinetic pleasures was as a response (or perhaps re-formulation) of the Cyrenaic proposition of a neutral state:

    Epicurean PathēCyrenaic Pathē
    Moving PleasureMoving Pleasure
    Stable Pleasure—
    —Neutral State
    PainPain

    With all of these typologies, I continue to wonder if these words were just general adjectives used to describe the diversity of pleasure, or whether they were strict technical categories. I am reminded that "no pleasure is an evil in itself" (KD 8 ) and that "pleasures would never differ from one another" (KD 9), so any hierarchy seems to diminish the unconditional proposition that "Pleasure is The Greatest Good" (not "Stable Pleasure is The Greatest Good to which Moving Pleasure is Subordinate"). Still ... there must be a significant reason this description exists.

  • Online
    Cassius
    05 - Administrator
    Points
    102,623
    Posts
    14,049
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    100.0 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 3:43 PM
    • #135
    Quote from Don

    Not from my reading. The original specifically says "And Epicurus in On Choices says as follows..." Then gives the quote.

    I didn't mean to dispute that the texts present this as a quote, just to point out that it is Diogenes Laertius presenting it out of context, so more than just relying on him to present it accurately, we're relying on him to have judged the context correctly.

    Quote from Nate

    t "pleasures would never differ from one another" (KD 9)

    That's a good one to remember in this context.

    Quote from Nate

    Still ... there must be a significant reason this description exists.

    To me, the issue of its being a response to Plato holding that pleasure could not be continuous is more than sufficient to justify its existence.


    Lots of good deep thinking in this thread so thank you again to all who are putting time into it.

  • Eikadistes
    Garden Bard
    Points
    14,574
    Posts
    848
    Quizzes
    3
    Quiz rate
    94.7 %
    Bookmarks
    10
    • July 16, 2022 at 3:59 PM
    • #136

    De Witt seems to think that this distinction (between "static" and "kinetic" pleasure) was profound:

    Quote

    “It was the discovery of static pleasure, without which continuity of pleasure was impossible, that resulted in the division of pleasures into static and kinetic. There was no call for such a division until the name of pleasure had been extended to denote the possession of health. On this point, however, as on many others, greater precision is possible. The modern use of the word static as opposed to kinetic is Aristotelian in origin. The Epicurean word is katastematikos, from katastema, explained in the lexicon as 'stable condition.’ It connotes, moreover, change of state, from action to rest. To Epicurus it denotes a normal state of pleasure to which the individual returns after kinetic pleasure, which is activity. For example, it is the comfortable feeling that follows after the satisfaction of hunger and thirst, the relaxed condition that follows after attending the theater, a public festival or a banquet. Exceptionally, it describes the return to normal after the joy of escape from peril of life.

    Since this innovation was, as it were, the keystone of the new hedonism, it is not surprising to learn that it was expounded in the letter addressed to the philosophers in Mytilene, which is rightly regarded as having been written in Lampsacus, nor that it was emphasized in other major writings and kept in the forefront by successors. That it was an innovation is made clear by a sound paragraph of Laertius. Discussing the divergence from Cyrenaic doctrine he quotes a phrase of Metrodorus: ‘Pleasure being thought of both as associated with motion and as static.’ Epicurus is quoted at slightly greater length: 'Serenity of mind and freedom from bodily pain are static pleasures, but joy and delight are seen to be associated with motion, that is, activity.' In both these passages modern usage calls for the adjective static; the Greek would demand catastematic. Static and kinetic would apply to the state of a stone, now lying on the ground, now sent hurtling through the air. Catastematic and kinetic would apply to the pleasure of a healthy Epicurean, now enjoying a quiet evening at home, now having a rollicking time at one of the monthly banquets.” (De Witt, Epicurus and His Philosophy 242-43)

    So, for De Witt, Kinetic pleasure is a rolling stone and Katastematic pleasure is a mossy stone?

  • Don
    ΕΠΙΚΟΥΡΕΙΟΣ (Epicurist)
    Points
    39,870
    Posts
    5,551
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    92.8 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 4:07 PM
    • #137
    Quote from Cassius

    I didn't mean to dispute that the texts present this as a quote, just to point out that it is Diogenes Laertius presenting it out of context, so more than just relying on him to present it accurately, we're relying on him to have judged the context correctly

    Hmm. If that's the concern, we would arguably have to throw out the majority of fragments and even Cicero since he also didn't necessarily cite context but cherry picked what he wanted.

  • Online
    Cassius
    05 - Administrator
    Points
    102,623
    Posts
    14,049
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    100.0 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 4:40 PM
    • #138
    Quote from Don

    If that's the concern, we would arguably have to throw out the majority of fragments and even Cicero since he also didn't necessarily cite context but cherry picked what he wanted.

    Well that is definitely a consideration as to all the fragments. Everyone was cherrypicking to suit their purposes, and even Diogenes Laertius was apparently following a system so he could present similar material on all the different philosophers.

  • Online
    Cassius
    05 - Administrator
    Points
    102,623
    Posts
    14,049
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    100.0 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 4:43 PM
    • #139
    Quote from Nate

    De Witt seems to think that this distinction (between "static" and "kinetic" pleasure) was profound:

    My interpretation of that, Nate, is that DeWitt is saying that indeed the designation of normal functioning without high-speed activity is definitely profound because that is what allows us to say that pleasure is continuous.

    I see the issue of whether this "normal functioning" is katastematic or kinetic, and whether the division makes any difference, as a totally different issue.

    If you define pleasure and pain as the only two states, then BY DEFINITION when you aren't feeling pain you are feeling pleasure, and that's regardless of what you happen to be doing or thinking about at the time.

  • Don
    ΕΠΙΚΟΥΡΕΙΟΣ (Epicurist)
    Points
    39,870
    Posts
    5,551
    Quizzes
    9
    Quiz rate
    92.8 %
    • July 16, 2022 at 7:33 PM
    • #140
    Quote from Cassius

    I didn't mean to dispute that the texts present this as a quote, just to point out that it is Diogenes Laertius presenting it out of context, so more than just relying on him to present it accurately, we're relying on him to have judged the context correctly

    I think the context is clear. I don't think Diogenes is trying to cherry pick either. Look at the full section where this occurs (I'm using Perseus/Hicks for ease of copying )

    Quote

    136 He differs from the Cyrenaics with regard to pleasure. They do not include under the term pleasure which is a state of rest, but only that which consists in motion. Epicurus admits both ; also pleasure of mind as well as of body, as he states in his work On Choice and Avoidance and in that On the Ethical End, and in the first book of his work On Human Life and in the epistle to his philosopher friends in Mytilene. So also Diogenes in the seventeenth book of his Epilecta, and Metrodorus in his Timocrates, whose actual words are : "Thus pleasure being conceived both as that species which consists in motion and that which is a state of rest." The words of Epicurus in his work On Choice are : "Peace of mind and freedom from pain are pleasures which imply a state of rest ; joy and delight are seen to consist in motion and activity."

    *Six* titles are referenced there from *three" Epicurean authors: Epicurus, Diogenes of Tarsus, and Metrodorus. There are two quotes, one from Epicurus, one from Metrodorus. All supporting the same thing. I put much more stock in Diogenes Laertius than I do Cicero. It seems to me DL was trying to get down (mostly) factual or at least anecdotal facts as opposed to Cicero who has a an agenda.

    PS. I keep getting frowny faces when I use parentheses. Please don't read more into it anybody. I fixed one in this post already.

Unread Threads

    1. Title
    2. Replies
    3. Last Reply
    1. Does The Wise Man Groan and Cry Out When On The Rack / Under Torture / In Extreme Pain? 17

      • Cassius
      • October 28, 2019 at 9:06 AM
      • General Discussion
      • Cassius
      • June 18, 2025 at 3:33 PM
    2. Replies
      17
      Views
      1k
      17
    3. Don

      June 18, 2025 at 3:33 PM
    1. New Translation of Epicurus' Works 1

      • Thanks 2
      • Eikadistes
      • June 16, 2025 at 3:50 PM
      • General Discussion
      • Eikadistes
      • June 16, 2025 at 6:32 PM
    2. Replies
      1
      Views
      226
      1
    3. Cassius

      June 16, 2025 at 6:32 PM
    1. Superstition and Friday the 13th 6

      • Like 2
      • Kalosyni
      • June 13, 2025 at 8:46 AM
      • General Discussion
      • Kalosyni
      • June 16, 2025 at 3:40 PM
    2. Replies
      6
      Views
      350
      6
    3. Eikadistes

      June 16, 2025 at 3:40 PM
    1. Epicurean Emporium 9

      • Like 3
      • Eikadistes
      • January 25, 2025 at 10:35 PM
      • General Discussion
      • Eikadistes
      • June 16, 2025 at 3:37 PM
    2. Replies
      9
      Views
      1.7k
      9
    3. Eikadistes

      June 16, 2025 at 3:37 PM
    1. The Religion of Nature - as supported by Lucretius' De Rerum Natura 2

      • Thanks 1
      • Kalosyni
      • June 12, 2025 at 12:03 PM
      • General Discussion
      • Kalosyni
      • June 16, 2025 at 11:42 AM
    2. Replies
      2
      Views
      299
      2
    3. Kalosyni

      June 16, 2025 at 11:42 AM

Latest Posts

  • Does The Wise Man Groan and Cry Out When On The Rack / Under Torture / In Extreme Pain?

    Don June 18, 2025 at 3:33 PM
  • Reconciling Cosma Raimondi and Diogenes Laertius On the Bull of Phalaris Question

    Cassius June 18, 2025 at 8:28 AM
  • Welcome Lamar

    Cassius June 17, 2025 at 11:00 AM
  • New Translation of Epicurus' Works

    Cassius June 16, 2025 at 6:32 PM
  • Superstition and Friday the 13th

    Eikadistes June 16, 2025 at 3:40 PM
  • New "TWENTIERS" Website

    Eikadistes June 16, 2025 at 3:38 PM
  • Epicurean Emporium

    Eikadistes June 16, 2025 at 3:37 PM
  • The Religion of Nature - as supported by Lucretius' De Rerum Natura

    Kalosyni June 16, 2025 at 11:42 AM
  • Is All Desire Painful? How Would Epicurus Answer?

    TauPhi June 15, 2025 at 9:23 PM
  • Best Translaton Of PDO1 To Feature At EpicureanFriends?

    Bryan June 14, 2025 at 2:44 PM

EpicureanFriends - Classical Epicurean Philosophy

  1. Home
    1. About Us
    2. Classical Epicurean Philosophy
  2. Wiki
    1. Getting Started
  3. Frequently Asked Questions
    1. Site Map
  4. Forum
    1. Latest Threads
    2. Featured Threads
    3. Unread Posts
  5. Texts
    1. Core Texts
    2. Biography of Epicurus
    3. Lucretius
  6. Articles
    1. Latest Articles
  7. Gallery
    1. Featured Images
  8. Calendar
    1. This Month At EpicureanFriends
Powered by WoltLab Suite™ 6.0.22
Style: Inspire by cls-design
Stylename
Inspire
Manufacturer
cls-design
Licence
Commercial styles
Help
Supportforum
Visit cls-design